This is the second post in an informal
series, the topic of which is “thinking.” If you have not read the
first post (it's fairly short) I encourage you to do so before
continuing.
Acute readers will have noticed that
the ending of Don't Burn Your Hands! clearly states that “we've
barely scratched the surface—more to come!” This obviously
implies that we were not done. But that was in August and here we are
closing in on December. So, if you would, allow me to apologize for
my failure to publish this post in a timely manner.
Having explored a broad generalization
of the concept of thinking (causal relationships), let us now begin
to break it apart and examine it more closely. One of the first
things we should notice is that thinking at this level is inherently
teleological, that is, it is directed
toward some end or goal. It does not wander
aimlessly, but rather, seeks something specific. What exactly does
that mean? If we take an example from the first post, specifically
the example of placing one's hand on the heated coil of a stove, we
know that this action will result in our hand being burned. But
examining the causal relationship between the act of placing our hand
on the coil and the result of our hand being burned is not properly
an end in itself. Rather, the end of such examination (thinking) is
presumably “how do I avoid burning my hand in the future?”
In this case, the end which our thinking is directed toward
would be the avoidance of burning one's hand.
For the purpose of these posts, the ends
which we direct our thoughts toward will be called
goods. Thus, the examination of the causal relationship
between the act of placing one's hand on a heated coil and the effect
of it being burned, is directed toward the good of avoiding
such effects in the future. Most people will agree that it is
desirable to not burn one's hand on the coil of a stove. In other
words, it is seen to be good to avoid such things. However, no
one deliberately directs their thoughts toward an end which they
believe to be destructive or bad. Ends are always seen as goods in
the mind of an individual. This leads us to the contrast between real
and apparent goods.
A real or genuine good, is an end which
is actually good for a person. The end of avoiding burning
one's hand, for example, would be considered a real or genuine good.
An apparent good, on the other hand, is a good which, while a person
may think or believe it to be genuinely beneficial for
them, in reality is not. We can easily conceive of a person
who desires to eat chocolate cake at every meal. Such an end would no
doubt be seen as a good in the mind of the individual, but would
nonetheless prove to be the opposite. This inevitably leads us to yet
another distinction. That of the short-term and long-term
effects or consequences of different ends.
The short-term effect of my avoiding
burning my hand can be seen as a real good because I do in fact avoid
burning my hand. The long-term effect would be the same. In this case
there is no difference between the short-term and long-term effects
when it comes to the end of “avoiding burning my hand.” Can the
same be said of the person whose end is the consumption of chocolate
cake at every meal? The short-term effect of eating chocolate cake
at every meal is simply the gratification of the desire to eat
chocolate cake at every meal. Again, in the mind of the individual,
this end is seen as a good. Even so, the long-term effect would be
quite different, the very least of which would be mild health
problems. In this case, the long-term effect of the end of “eating
chocolate cake at every meal” reveals itself to be, not a real or
genuine good, but on the contrary, an apparent good.
On the basis of what has been said, we
can make several conclusions about the essence of goods.
First, real goods are ends which actually produce
beneficial effects, with an added emphasis on the long-term.
In many circumstances, the short-term or immediate effect of a real
good, is not seen to be good or beneficial at all. When a person who
desires to lose weight begins to eat healthy or work out, for
instance, the short-term circumstances are generally undesirable.
Prior to working out this person was overweight. Now that they have
begun working out, they are still overweight, but now they are tired
and sore as well! Thus, this person must tolerate a short-term pain
or discomfort in order to attain their desired end in the long-term,
which is a real good.
Next, we find that apparent goods
are ends which are expected to produce beneficial effects and
generally emphasize the short-term. Put differently, apparent
goods have a tendency to focus on the immediate effect of an
end or good. Procrastinating on a project may seem to be desirable in
the short-term, but oftentimes such ends produce hazardous effects in
the long-term. As discussed in Lesson VIII: Self-Deception and
Learning, a characteristic of self-deception is seen in
fulfilling immediate desires while simultaneously ignoring future
consequences.
A person may opt to tolerate a given
pain or discomfort in the short-term, in order to enjoy a real good
in the long term. While another person may solely be focused on an
apparent good in the short-term, at the expense of the long-term.
Herein lies the difference between good and bad choices. In one
instance, a person takes into account the short-term and the
long-term effects, and evaluates them as goods. In another, only the
short-term or immediate effects are considered and evaluated as
goods.
I do realize that this is a lot of
information, but it is a necessary foundation to understand the
forthcoming posts on this topic.
No comments:
Post a Comment